3.2 UNCONSCIOUS MIND PRIOR TO FRUED:
The term “unconscious “was coined by the 18th-century German romantic philosopher Friedrich Schelling and later introduced into English by the poet and essayist Samuel Taylor Coleridge.
The unconscious mind (or the unconscious) consists of the processes in the mind that occur automatically and are not available to introspection. It include thought processes, memory, affect, and motivation. Even though these processes exist well under the surface of conscious awareness they are theorized to exert an impact on behavior.
Paracelsus is credited as the first to make mention of an unconscious aspect of cognition in his work Von den Krankheiten ("About illnesses", 1567), and his clinical methodology created a cogent system that is regarded by some as the beginning of modern scientific psychology. Several concepts of unconscious in his characterizations can be seen in the plays of William Shakespeare. Western philosophers such as Espinoza, Leibniz, A Schopenhauer[i], Fichte, Hegel[ii]-[iii], Kierkegaard, and Nietzsche, developed a view of the mind which foreshadowed Freud's theories. Psychologist Jacques Van Rillaer points out that, "the unconscious was not discovered by Freud.
In 1890, when psychoanalysis was still unheard of, William James, in his monumental treatise on psychology, examined the way Schopenhauer, von Hartmann[iv], Janet, Binet and others had
used the term 'unconscious' and 'subconscious'". The unconscious, cerebral activity and debth psychology were well known to the nineteenth century psychologists and physicians who practiced psychiatry( like Eugene Bleuler and Emil Kraeplein).
[i] The inward reluctance with which any one accepts the
world as merely his idea, warns him that this view of it, however true it may
be, is nevertheless one-sided, adopted in consequence of some arbitrary
abstraction. And yet it is a conception from which he can never free himself. The
defectiveness of this view will be corrected in the next book by means of a
truth which is not so immediately certain as that from which we start here; a
truth at which we can arrive only by deeper research and more severe
abstraction, by the separation of what is different and the union of what is
identical. This truth, which must be very serious and impressive if not awful
to every one, is that a man can also say and must say, "the world is my
will."......................................... We, however, who
consistently occupy the standpoint of philosophy, must be satisfied here with
negative know ledge, content to have reached the utmost limit of the positive.
We have recognised the inmost nature of the world as will, and all its
phenomena as only the objec tivity of will ; and we have followed this
objectivity from the unconscious working of obscure forces of Nature up to the
completely conscious action of man. Therefore we shall by no means evade the
consequence, that with the free denial, the surrender of the will, all those
phenomena are also abolished ; that constant strain and effort without end
and without rest at all the grades of objectivity, in which and through which
the world consists ; the multi farious forms succeeding each other in
gradation ; the whole manifestation of the will; and, finally, also the
universal forms of this manifestation, time and space, andalso its last
fundamental form, subject and object ; all are abolished. No will :
no idea, no world.
Before us there is
certainly only nothingness. the will to foe, which" we ourselves are as
it is our world. That we abhor annihilation so greatly, is simply another
expression of the fact that we so strenu ously will life, and are nothing but
this will, and know nothing besides it But if we turn our glance from our own
needy and embarrassed condition to those who have overcome the world, in whom
the will, having attained to perfect self-knowledge, found itself again in
all, and then freely denied itself, and who then merely wait to see the last
trace of it vanish with the body which it animates ; then, instead of
the restless striving and effort, instead of the constant transition from
wish to fruition, and from joy to sorrow, instead of the never-satisfied and
never-dying hope which constitutes the life of the man who wills, we shall
see that peace which is above all reason, that perfect calm of the spirit,
that deep rest, that inviolable confidence and serenity, the mere reflec tion
of which in the countenance, as Raphael and Cor- reggio have represented it,
is an entire and certain gospel ; only knowledge remains, the will lias
vanished. We look with deep and painful longing upon this state, beside which
the misery and wretchedness of our own is brought out clearly by the
contrast. Yet this is the only con sideration which can afford us lasting
consolation, when, on the one hand, we have recognised incurable suffering
and .^ndless misery as essential to the manifestation of will, the
world ; and, on the other hand, see the world pass away with the
abolition of will, and retain before us only empty nothingness. Thus, in this
way, by contem plation of the lii e and conduct of saints, whom it is
certainly rarely granted us to meet with in our own ex perience, but who are
brought before our eyes by their written history, and, witli the stamp of
inner truth, byart, we must banish the dark impression oi that nothing ness
which we discern behind all virtue and holiness as their final goal, and
which we fear as children fear the dark ; we must not even evade it like
the Indians, through myths and meaningless words, such as reabsorption in
Brahma or the Nirvana of the Buddhists. Kather do we freely acknowledge that
what remains after the entire abolition of will is for all those who are
still full of will certainly nothing ; but, conversely, to those in whom
the will has turned and has denied itself, this our world, which is so real,
with all its suns and milky-ways is nothing. 11 This is also just the Prajna-
are no more. (Cf. J. J. Schmidt,Paramita of the Buddhists, the " Ueber
das Mahajana und Prat-"beyond all knowledge," i.e., the
schna-Paramita.") point at which subject and object.The
World as Will and Representation by
Arthur
Schopenhauer,
translated by R B Haldane and J.
KempFourth Book .
|
http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/The_World_as_Will_and_Representation/Fourth_Book
[ii]
Title: The Unconscious
Abyss: Hegel's Anticipation of Psychoanalysis Author:
Mills, Jon
Publisher: New York: SUNY Press, 2002 Reviewed By: Marilyn Nissim Sabat, Winter 2005, pp. 65-68
Publisher: New York: SUNY Press, 2002 Reviewed By: Marilyn Nissim Sabat, Winter 2005, pp. 65-68
Preliminary Rather, in showing that Hegel anticipated
Freud, Mills seeks to accomplish two goals: first, he aims to restore the
unconscious to the status and role it has in the Freudian body of writings;
secondly, Mills aims to motivate the transformation of psychoanalysis into what
he calls a “process psychology” or, equivalently, a “dialectical
psychoanalysis.” Were this to come about, a sea change in clinical thinking and
clinical work should follow. Thus, the showing of Hegel’s anticipation of
psychoanalysis (a highly successful tour de force by Mills), is intended to
evoke something like the following reflections: if Hegel anticipated
psychoanalysis, then psychoanalysis can benefit greatly, at the very least,
from Hegel’s dialectical method (Mills repeatedly states in the book that he
does not advocate adoption of Hegel’s philosophical stance tout court).
However, as Mills notes in his introductory chapter on
the prehistory of Hegel’s notion of the unconscious abyss, the Hegelian
dialectic is radically different from the Fichtean thesis-antithesis-synthesis;
for Hegel, rather, every “synthesis” is a new beginning, and this places the
emphasis properly: the dialectical process is ever ongoing. Perhaps Hoffman has
not fully appreciated this aspect of the Hegelian dialectic.
The Unconscious Abyss is in many ways a
remarkable book, particularly, as will be illustrated below, in the manner and
content of Mills exposition of both Hegel’s and Freud’s ideas. Hegel has
benefited from having quite a few superb expositors and interpreters; While it
contains many significant quotes from both Hegel and Freud, the book clearly is
the product of an extraordinary process of internalization of Hegel’s writings
and thought. Mills gives us Hegel from the inside, so to speak, Hegel as Mills’
lived experience of his thought, Mills’ love for and mastery of Hegel’s system,
and Freud’s as well. Thus, Mills’ presentation of Hegel is neither merely
expository nor merely interpretive; rather, it is a representation of Hegel
infused throughout by a vision of the whole and by Mills’ conviction not only
that Hegel anticipated Freud, but that if psychoanalysis is to have a future,
qua psychoanalysis, that is, then it must be grounded in core ideas of Hegelianism.
From a critical perspective, it must be said that the
marriage of Hegel and Freud is based on, so to speak, a pre-nuptial agreement;
that is, Mills assumes that Freud’s philosophical perspective was not
physicalist reduction (or positivist), as Hegel’s was not. This is certainly a
plausible view of Freud for which many have argued, given that Freud’s own
remarks are notoriously ambiguous on this point. Were Freud a physicalist
reductionist, his system would be radically incompatible with Hegel’s. In the
conclusion of this review, I will make some further remarks on this point.
The best way to characterize The Unconscious Abyss
is by discussing the meaning of the phrase itself, as Mills understands it.
However, before doing so it is necessary to discuss some of the most important
factors that lead Mills to believe not only that Hegel anticipated Freud, but
that Hegel provides a philosophical grounding for Freud’s conception of the
psyche that gives psychoanalysis needed credibility.
For Mills, the view that psychoanalysis ought to be
construed as a “process psychology” or a “dialectical psychoanalysis” is the
outcome of comprehending the development of the ego from its inception in the
unconscious abyss to its attainment of mature self-consciousness. This is so
because Hegel’s notion of the inception of the psyche as “drive,” and as
ceaseless self-activity and change is identical to Freud’s notion of “drive,”
and anything that is in ceaseless change is necessarily in a process of
becoming. Most important is a point Mills reiterates throughout his study:
following Hegel, Mills insists not only that the ego (the ego in the psychoanalytic
and Hegelian senses) originates in the unconscious; in addition and most
importantly, he insists that the unconscious ontologically, logically, and
developmentally precedes consciousness and self-consciousness and is the
dynamic root of human psychic and psychosocial development. It follows from
this that failing to appreciate this relation between consciousness and the
unconscious amounts to abandoning psychoanalysis.
Mills is of course not the first psychoanalyst/theorist
to deplore what is taken to be the jettisoning of the Freudian unconscious.
Defense of the unconscious has come from a variety of sources, including some
theorists who proclaim that Freud was a physicalist reductionist and that the
unconscious consists primarily of drives that originate biologically, i.e., in
the body where the body is construed as pure materiality. The problem with this
perspective is that it inevitably culminates either in an untenable pure
materialism that denies freedom or in some form or other of psychophysical
dualism, for example epiphenomenalism, which Freud at times espoused. Mills’
defense of the Freudian unconscious rejects the view that Freud was a
reductionist, even though Freud understood correctly that drives originate in
the biological body. This is one of the crucial points that Mills believes is
resolved by the Hegelian perspective. The issue to be resolved is this: how do
we understand both that drives originate in the biological body and at the same
time that this is not a reductionist claim?
The solution lies in the rejection of mind-body dualism.
The Hegelian philosophy is entirely monistic, and its method is dialectic. In
this perspective, subjectivity and substance (nature, materiality) are
dialectically interpenetrated such that the progress of Spirit (Mind) towards
freedom is a progress from substance to subject. In other words, when subject
recognizes nature as its own externalized self, spirit will have returned to
its beginning prior to its own self-diremption (splitting into Nature and
Mind). There is no dualism, then, because subject and nature are ontologically
the same. Thus, physicalist reductionism (or positivism), the view that there
is a nature that exists entirely independently of subjectivity, is untenable
within the Hegelian monistic perspective. Importantly, however, Mills cautions
that he does not advocate acceptance of Hegel’s entire system. For example, we
need not accept Hegel’s notion of all of human history as the odyssey of Spirit
towards Absolute Knowledge, i.e., freedom consequent upon Spirit’s
reconciliation with its own alienated self, Nature.
[iii]
Historical Origins of the Abyss:Hegel himself did not
originate the notion of the unconscious abyss. Rather he took it over in large
measure from Boehme, neo-Platonism, and Schelling. The concept of the abyss (Ungrund)
derives from Boehme's theosophic Christianity. Inspired by the study of
Plotinus,(3)
Boehme radically reconceptualized God as the ens manifestativum sui,
"the being whose essence is to reveal itself."(4)
Boehme developed an elementary form of dialectic. In this dialectic, positive
and negative polarities emerge out of the Godhead's original undifferentiated
non-being (das Nichts), and these unfold through orderly stages of
manifestation as it ascends toward absolute self-consciousness.(5) At
one time, scholars thought that Boehme's term Ungrund originated in
the Gnostic 'abyss,' since there are shared similarities between the two.(6)
But Koyré has cogently disputed this claim, interpreting Boehme's notion of the
abyss as the "ground without a ground."(7)
Before the divine Ungrund emerges, there is no source of
determination, there is nothing; the Ungrund is merely "unfathomable"
and "incomprehensible." The Ungrund is the uncertainty which
precedes the divine will's arousing itself to self-awareness.(8)
Furthermore, Boehme's Ungrund acts as a subject who desires: "it
'seeks,' it 'longs,' it 'sees,' and it 'finds'."(9)While
Hegel does give testimony to Boehme,(10)
he probably owes more to Proclus (through Creuzer), Plotinus, Erigena, and
Schelling.(11)
Boehme's impact on Schelling was considerable; and Schelling was among the very
first philosophers to underscore the importance of the unconscious and the role
of irrationality in human experience.(12)
However, it was two arch-rationalists, Leibniz and Kant, who paved the way for
this development. In the New Essays on Human Understanding, Leibniz
propounded a theory of unconscious petits perceptions. Kant, in his
Anthropology, discussed the nature of "obscure presentations" (dunkele
Vorstellungen) that remain just below the level of conscious awareness.(13)
Schelling's revision of Kant's and Fichte's transcendental idealism together
with Schelling's own philosophy of identity (Identitätsphilosophie)
and philosophy of nature (Naturphilosophie) led to one of the first
systematic conceptualizations of the unconscious.(14) Hegel on the Unconscious Abyss: Implications for
Psychoanalysis. Jon Mills © published in The Owl of Minerva, 1996, 28
(1), 59-75.
[iv] PHILOSOPHY OP THE UNCONSCIOUS. BT EDUARD VON HABTMANN. SPECULATIVE RESULTS ACCORDING TO THE INDUCTIVE METHOD OF PHYSICAL SCIENCE. AUTHORISED TRANSLATION
BY WILLIAM CHATTERTON COUPLAND, M.A., B.Sc IN THREE VOLUMES. VOL. III. SECOND EDITION. LONDON: KEGAN PAUL, TRENCH, TRUBNER, & CO. L PATERNOSTER HOUSE,CHARING CROSS ROAD. 1893.
http://archive.org/stream/philosophyoftheu032424mbp/philosophyoftheu032424mbp_djvu.txt
If we may assume that the former errors might be
got
rid of in the judgment of a large number of
individuals,
the latter source of error, on the contrary, weighs
so much
the heavier. Whoever knows how powerful is the un-
conscious bias of thought and judgment by the will,
by
instincts and feelings, will immediately allow the
great
importance of the errors thereby rendered possible.
Let any one reflect how easily unpleasant
impressions
are blotted out of the mind and how pleasant ones
re-
main, so that even an event or adventure
disagreeable
enough in reality appears in memory in the most
charming
light (jurat meminisse malorum) ; in consequence of
this
the recapitulating memory must attain to a far more
favourable summing up of the pleasure-content of
personal
life than a review of the pleasure and pain
actually felt
in the course of life undistorted by the glasses of
memory
would yield. What memory is unable to accomplish in
the way of hushing up really felt pain, the
instinct of
hope most certainly accomplishes for future feeling
(comp. below No. 12), and the balance of the past
will
be involuntarily falsified by all younger persons
by the
introduction of the idea of a future which is
purged by
hope of the main causes of past pain without the
causes
of pain hereafter to be added being taken into
account.
Thus it is not the true life as it actually was and
will be, but as it is exhibited to the uncritical eye in the embel-
lishing mirror of memory and in the deceptive
roseate
hue of hope that is used for drawing the balance
between
the sum of pleasure and the sum of pain ; and hence
it is
no wonder if a result appears to be yielded which
little
enough agrees with reality.
Let one consider, further, that the foolish vanity
of man
goes so far as to prefer to seem rather than to be
not
merely well but also happy, so that every one
carefully
hides where the shoe pinches, and tries to make a
show of
opulence, content ment, and happiness which he does
not
at all possess. This source of error falsifies the
sentence
that one passes on others according to what they
express
and reveal of the balance of pleasure and pain of
their life, just as the two just-named sources of error the judgment
on their own part. If one, however, judges
according to
what other people are wont to declare concerning
the sum
of happiness of their whole life, it is clear that
we have
here to deal with the product of the two mentioned
errors. One already sees from this with what
caution
we must accept the judgment of mankind on their own
felicity.
Lastly, when we consider, as is a priori to be
expected,
that the same unconscious will which has created
beings
with these instincts and passions will also through
these
instincts and passions influence conscious thinking
in the
direction of the same life-impulse, we should
rather only
wonder how the instinctive love of life should come
to
be able in consciousness to condemn this same life;
for
the same Unconscious which wills life, and,
moreover, for
its quite special ends wills just this life in
spite of its
wretchedness, will certainly not omit to fit out
the crea-
tures of life with just as many illusions us they
need, in
order not merely to make life supportable, but also
to
leave over enough love of life, elasticity, and
freshness for the life-tasks to be accomplished by them and claiming
all their energy, and thus to cozen them concerning
the
misery of their existence.
No comments:
Post a Comment